There are arguments both for and against euthanasia and assisted suicide.
Some of the
main arguments are outlined below
Arguments for
euthanasia and assisted suicide
There are
two main types of argument used to support the practices of euthanasia and
assisted suicide. They are the:
•
ethical
argument – that
people should have freedom of choice, including the right to control their own
body and life (as long as they do not abuse any other person’s rights), and
that the state should not create laws that prevent people being able to
choose when and how they die
•
pragmatic
argument – that
euthanasia, particularly passive euthanasia, is already a widespread practice
(allegedly), just not one that people are willing to admit to, so it is
better to regulate euthanasia properly
The pragmatic
argument is discussed in more detail below.
Pragmatic
argument
The pragmatic
argument states that many of the practices used in end of life care
are a type of euthanasia in all but name.
For example,
there is the practice of making a ‘do not attempt cardiopulmonary
resuscitation' (DNACPR) order, where a person requests not to receive
treatment if their heart stops beating or they stop breathing.
Critics have
argued that DNACPR is a type of passive euthanasia because a person is denied
treatment that could potentially save their life.
Another
controversial practice is known as palliative sedation. This is where a person
who is experiencing extreme suffering, for which there is no effective
treatment, is put to sleep using sedative medication. For example, palliative
sedation is often used to treat burns victims who are expected to die.
While
palliative sedation is not directly carried out for the purpose of ending
lives, many of the sedatives used carry a risk of shortening a person’s
lifespan. Therefore, it could be argued that palliative sedation is a type
of active euthanasia.
The pragmatic
argument is that if euthanasia in these forms is being carried out anyway,
society might as well legalise it and ensure that it is properly regulated.
It should be
stressed that the above interpretations of DNACPR and palliative sedation are
very controversial and are not accepted by most doctors, nurses and palliative
care specialists.
Read more about
the alternatives to
euthanasia for responses to these interpretations.
Arguments
against euthanasia and assisted suicide
There are four
main types of argument used by people who are against euthanasia and
assisted suicide. They are known as the:
•
religious
argument – that
these practices can never be justified for religious reasons, for example many
people believe that only God has the right to end a human life
•
‘slippery
slope’ argument – this is
based on the concern that legalising euthanasia could lead to significant
unintended changes in our healthcare system and society at large that we would
later come to regret
•
medical ethics
argument – that
asking doctors, nurses or any other healthcare professional to carry out
euthanasia or assist in a suicide would be a violation of fundamental medical
ethics
•
alternative
argument – that
there is no reason for a person to suffer either mentally or physically
because effective end of life treatments are available; therefore,
euthanasia is not a valid treatment option but represents a failure on the part
of the doctor involved in a person’s care
Religious
argument
The most common
religious argument is that human beings are the sacred creation of God, so
human life is by extension sacred.
Only God should
choose when a human life ends, so committing an act of euthanasia or assisting
in suicide is acting against the will of God and is sinful.
This belief, or
variations on it, is shared by members of the Christian, Jewish and Islamic
faiths.
The issue is
more complex in Hinduism and Buddhism. Scholars from both faiths have
argued that euthanasia and assisted suicides are ethically acceptable acts in
some circumstances, but these views do not have universal support among Hindus
and Buddhists.
‘Slippery
slope’ argument
The slippery
slope argument is based on the idea that once a healthcare service, and by
extension the government, starts killing its own citizens, a line is crossed
that should never have been crossed and a dangerous precedent has been set.
The concern is
that a society that allows voluntary euthanasia will gradually change its
attitudes to include non-voluntary and then involuntary euthanasia.
Also, legalised
voluntary euthanasia could eventually lead to a wide range of unforeseen
consequences, such as those described below.
•
Very ill people
who need constant care or people with severe disabilities may feel pressured to
request euthanasia so that they are not a burden to their family.
•
Legalising
euthanasia may discourage research into palliative treatments,
and possibly prevent cures for people with terminal illnesses being found.
•
Occasionally, doctors
may be mistaken about a person’s diagnosis and outlook, and the person may
choose euthanasia due to being wrongly told that they have a terminal
condition.
Medical ethics
argument
The medical
ethics argument, which is similar to the ‘slippery slope’
argument, states that legalising euthanasia would violate one of the most
important medical ethics, which, in the words of the International Code of
Medical Ethics, is: ‘A doctor must always bear in mind the obligation of
preserving human life from conception’.
Asking doctors
to abandon their obligation to preserve human life could damage the
doctor–patient relationship. Causing death on a regular basis could become
a routine administrative task for doctors, leading to a lack of compassion when
dealing with elderly, disabled or terminally ill people.
In turn, people
with complex health needs or severe disabilities could become distrustful of
their doctor’s efforts and intentions. They may think that their doctor
would rather ‘kill them off’ than take responsibility for a complex and
demanding case.
Alternative
argument
The alternative
argument is that advances in palliative care and mental health treatment mean
there is no reason why any person should ever feel that they are suffering
intolerably, whether it is physical or mental suffering or both.
According to
this argument, if a person is given the right care, in the right
environment, there should be no reason why they are unable to have a
dignified and painless natural death.
No comments:
Post a Comment